pilipili

 

Impact Ethics

Mitochondrial Replacement

SELECT MEDIA CONTRIBUTIONS

  • Pullen, LC. (9 Feb 2016). . Medscape.
  • Scrutti, S. (5 Feb 2016). . Medical Daily.
  •  Baylis, F. et al. (3 Feb 2016). . GENES - Genetic Expert News Service.
  • Vogel, G. (3 Feb 2016). . Science-AAAS.
  • Claiborne, A.B., English, R.A., & Kahn, J.P. (3 Feb 2016). . Science-AAAS.
  • Achenbach, J. (3 Feb 2016) . The Washington Post.
  • National Academies of Science. (3 Feb 2016). . Science News.
  • Hamilton, G. (23 Sept 2015). . Nature News.
  • Shoot, B. (28 Feb 2015). The Guardian.
  • Cussins, J. (22 Jan 2015). Biopolitical Times.
  • Darnovsky, M. (23 Feb 2014). New York Times.
  • Check Hayden, E. (15 Oct 2013). Nature.
  • Stein, R. (9 Oct 2013). . NPR.

SELECT IMPACT ETHICS BLOGS

  • Baylis, F. (2 Aug 2017). . Impact Ethics.

  • Baylis, F. (25 Feb - 6 Mar 2016). @NEJM Ask the Authors & Experts: Mitochondrial replacement techniques – implications for the clinical community. NEJM Group Open Forum.

  • Baylis, F. (3 Feb 2016). . Impact Ethics.

  • Baylis, F. (23 Feb 2015). . Impact Ethics.

  • Baylis, F. (2 Jul 2013). . Impact Ethics.

  • Wolbring, G. (27 May 2015). . Impact Ethics.

SELECT PUBLICATIONS

  • Baylis, F. (2017). . Bioethics, 31(1), 7‐19. DOI:10.1111/bioe.12309

  • Baylis, F. (9-10 September 2015). Is there a compelling need for mitochondrial replacement? Invitational symposium Me medicine vs. We medicine: Personalised medicine, individual choice and the common good. Amsterdam, The Netherlands.
  • Baylis, F. (1 March 2014). Against mitochondrial replacement. American Philosophical Association Central Division, One Hundred Eleventh Annual Meeting, Committee on Philosophy and Medicine: Ethics in Reproductive Technology, Chicago, USA.
  • Baylis F. (2013) [PDF - 207 KB]. Reproductive BioMedicine Online, 26, 531-534. This article on mitochondrial replacement technology briefly explains and defends the legitimacy of such terms as 'three-parent embryos', 'three-parent babies' and 'three-person IVF'. Next, it reviews select ethical objections to mitochondrial replacement technology that fall into four, sometimes overlapping, categories: (i) harms to egg providers; (ii) harms to potential offspring and future generations; (iii) harms to specific interest groups; and (iv) harms to society. Although these ethical objections taken together are cause for concern, it is suggested that the development and future use of mitochondrial replacement technology is inevitable.
  • Baylis, F. (2009). [PDF 283 KB]. International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics, 2(2), 75-96. In April 2007, as part of its public consultation initiative, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) in the United Kingdom published Hybrids and chimeras: A consultation on the ethical and social implications of creating human/animal embryos in research. This HFEA document identifies a number of possible arguments against the creation of human/animal embryos. One of these arguments concerns the worry that human/animal embryos “might be transferred to a woman to create babies with some animal DNA in them.” Although the HFEA dismisses this slippery slope argument, I argue that this possible future is not as farfetched as one might think. For example, human admixed embryos might be transferred to women in an effort to prevent the transmission of mitochondrial diseases. The ethical acceptability of this possible future practice is examined from different feminist perspectives with a focus on issues of reproductive freedom and social justice.

SELECT POLICY CONTRIBUTIONS

  • Baylis, F. (2016). . Royal Society of Canada Expert Panel Report on Claiborne, A., English, R., & Kahn, J. (Eds.). (3 Feb 2016). . Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

Recent News

On the 3 February 2016, the National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine released a report, . With this report, written at the request of the Food and Drug Administration, the United States is poised to proceed with research involving mitochondrial replacement. Authored by the on the Ethical and Social Policy Considerations of Novel Techniques for Prevention of Maternal Transmission of Mitochondrial DNA Diseases, it makes a number of important contributions to the ethics and policy debates. In sum, the Committe concluded that "it is ethically permissible to conduct clinical investigations of MRT [Mitochondrial replacement techniques]. To ensure that clinical investigations of MRT were performed ethically, however, certain conditions and principles would need to govern the conduct of clinical investigations and potential future implementation of MRT." Françoise Baylis was an external reviewer and provided comments on an earlier draft of the report. Several NTE members' was referenced in the final published version. Read more .

Overview

For the past few years there has been considerable debate about the ethics of germ-line genetic interventions, with scientists in different countries arguing for the clinical use of mitochondrial replacement technology to avoid the birth of children with mitochondrial disease.

Diseases resulting from mutations in mitochondrial DNA can include poor growth, deafness, blindness, heart disease, liver disease, kidney disease, learning disabilities, loss of muscle coordination, muscle weakness, and neurological problems. Preclinical research suggests it may be possible to avoid these diseases by replacing disease-linked mitochondrial DNA with healthy mitochondrial DNA from another woman’s egg. With the use of this technology, women with diseased mitochondrial DNA could have genetically-related children free of mitochondrial disease. Use of this technology, however, involves crossing the boundary of germline genetic manipulation. In Canada this is prohibited by .

While mitochondrial manipulation has not been the subject of much discussion in Canada, there has been considerable debate about this in both the United States and the United Kingdom.

United States

In February 2014, the Cellular, Tissue and Gene Therapies Advisory Committee of the U.S. Food and Drug Administration ( [182 - KB]) met to discuss human egg modification to prevent the transmission of mitochondrial disease ( [PDF - 334 KB]). [PDF - 88 KB] concluding that the various ethical objections to the science were serious cause for concern. Many speakers at the advisory committee meeting , noting that egg modification could "alter the human species" and "open the door to genetically-modified children." The FDA "heard the concerns expressed at the advisory committee meeting,” and determined that "there probably aren't enough data in animals or in vitro to conclusively move on to human trials without answering a few additional questions." On January 27, 2015 the Institute of Medicine appointed a to study the "" A of was released 3 Feburary 2016.

United Kingdom

In 2013, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (the UK’s regulator overseeing the use of gametes and embryos in fertility treatment and research) [PDF - 390 KB] as a technique to avoid serious mitochondrial diseases. Although it recognized “strong ethical concerns that some respondents to the consultation expressed,” the HFEA concluded that there was “general support for permitting mitochondria replacement in the UK, so long as it is safe enough to offer in a treatment setting and is done so within a regulatory framework.”

This conclusion marked a significant departure from past practice, and the HFEA’s findings were not reflective of adequate public consultation. On February 27, 2014, the UK government [PDF - 167 KB] on regarding mitochondrial replacement, in which it called for “any new evidence since the 2013 update.” On March 21, 2014, the Center for Genetics and Society [PDF - 312 KB] in response to the new call for evidence. This letter urged the HFEA to “carefully examine and thoroughly review and follow up on the wide range of safety and efficacy concerns raised by the FDA committee” on mitochondrial replacement, and to provide “an accurate summary of the current state of expert and scientific understanding.” Previously, Françoise Baylis [PDF - 408 KB], which warned that for the UK to undertake the change “without consulting its international partners would create a very serious precedent.”

On February 3, 2015 members of the UK the . These regulations were to allow "mitochondrial donation techniques to be used under licence as part of IVF treatment with the aim of preventing the transmission of serious mitochondrial disease from mother to child." The House Lords approved the on February 24, 2015 which came into force on October 29, 2015. The "through which applications can be considered from clinicians wanting to offer the two techniques set out in the regulations". For more information on the licensable techniques, visit .

Last updated August 2017.